К отъезду Marat Davletbaev в Рим ничего лучше чем Мандельштам про Чаадаева и сказать нельзя:

«Когда Борис Годунов, предвосхищая мысль Петра, отправил за границу русских молодых людей, ни один из них не вернулся. Они не вернулись по той простой причине, что нет пути обратно от бытия к небытию, что в душной Москве задохнулись бы вкусившие бессмертной весны неумирающего Рима. Но ведь и первые голуби не вернулись обратно в ковчег. Чаадаев был первым русским, в самом деле, идейно, побывавшим на Западе и нашедшим дорогу обратно».

Опасное это дело, эта ваша философия.

The Guardian, http://www.theguardian.com/education/2016/mar/15/why-philosophers-make-unsuitable-life-partners:

«It is said that on a trip to the US in the 1920s a German sociologist was astonished at the domestic arrangements of his American colleagues. How can you get any serious work done, he asked, without servants? The duties of a spouse and parent apparently do not sit well with deep thought and research, unless eased by paid help.

This makes me wonder whether “parentism” might be a problem to consider alongside sexism, at least in certain branches of academia. The two often go together, but they need not. Consider the student parlour game of puzzling over who among the major philosophical thinkers had a conventional home life.

In the ancient Greek world, Socrates was married with children but never got round to writing anything down. Plato, as far as we know, never married. Aristotle did marry, and one of his major works, The Nicomachean Ethics, is named after his son. But in later centuries the record is astonishing.

St Augustine (“grant me chastity, but not yet”) fathered an illegitimate child, but then became a celibate priest. Aquinas and the philosophers of the middle ages were all churchmen. In the 17th and 18th centuries, virtually all of the canonical figures were domestically unconventional. Hobbes, Locke, Hume, Adam Smith, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant and Bentham all went unmarried. Bishop Berkeley married late but had no children. Jean-Jacques Rousseau eventually married his lover Thérèse Levasseur, but abandoned all of his five children to foundling homes. This did not stop him writing a treatise, Emile, on the proper upbringing of children.

Closer to our own time, John Stuart Mill married late in life and had no children of his own. Schopenhauer, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Sartre and Wittgenstein were all unmarried and childless. Marx gave up philosophy, turning to economics and politics, when his children were still young.

There are exceptions. Hegel married and had children. And in the 20th century AJ Ayer and Betrand Russell brought up the averages by marrying lavishly, though reproducing modestly. But it is a remarkable tradition.

What about the major women philosophers? Of those who are widely known, Mary Wollstonecraft produced her major works before producing her children, and tragically died from complications after the birth of her second child, who would become Mary Shelley. Simone de Beauvoir, Hannah Arendt, Simone Weil and Iris Murdoch, were all childless.

What explains this extraordinary correlation? It could be pure coincidence, but other hypotheses press for consideration. One is that the sheer oddity of philosophers makes them unsuitable life partners. Another is that domestic bliss dulls the philosophical edge. A third is that the problem lies in the nature of the deepest, most fundamental, philosophical work. If genius is “the infinite capacity for taking pains”, it wouldn’t seem to leave much time for anything else.

Nevertheless, few are on the level of Spinoza or Kierkegaard. For ordinary mortals our research requires only a finite capacity for taking pains, which ought to be compatible with a normal home life. In fact, in a recent survey in my faculty, although many people report that they struggle to achieve an acceptable life-work balance, those caring for children seem to do better than those who are not. And this makes sense. If you are looking after your children it puts your academic work into perspective. Maybe it isn’t the most important thing in the world after all.

The trouble is that if you don’t think your research and writing are the most important thing, at least in your own world, you probably won’t do as much of it as you could. And this is how the academic careers of parents, especially mothers, can stall. Once upon a time, we would have said: “That’s the choice you make”. Now we know that there is such a thing as “indirect discrimination”. We need to define a new model of academic progression that is fair to everyone. And a start would be to make advancement dependent on what academics do during normal working hours, rather than in their evenings and weekends.»

вывод войск из Сирии

Пока по выходу из Сирии ничего не ясно, но ещё меньше я понимаю бессмысленную фразу «Россия потерпела поражение в Сирии». Вы это серьёзно?

Победить» или «проиграть» в этом постмодернистском «проекте» невозможно в принципе, здесь нельзя даже этой бинарной оппозицией оперировать.

Все внешние акторы в такого рода проектах исключительно «решают свои задачи». И надо через эту призму смотреть на происходящее.

В данном случае можно и нужно поставить вопросы: какие на самом деле цели ставились и задачи решались? и что в итоге было достигнуто?

Только вот боюсь, что вменяемый ответ мы если и узнаем, то только в чьих-то мемуарах и ещё очень не скоро. Всё остальное это спекуляции.

Легко впасть в примитивную риторику «о поражении России в Сирии», но это очевидная расписка в полном непонимании происходящего.

Прежде чем говорить о «поражении» сначала нужно определиться с тем, что вы в случае с сирийским конфликтом для России под этим понимаете.

Вот говорят о кризисе бумажных книг, а я между тем еле успел купить вчера в Циолковском только что вышедший сборник переводов Бодрийяра.

Но сейчас читаю не его, а последнюю книгу директора Стратфора «Горячие точки». Он уже целую книгу про европейский кризис успел написать.

Геополитика, конечно, не философия, но с другой стороны, у меня сейчас идёт курс «Европейская история идей», где мы начали с «идеи Европы».

И тогда это всё ложится как нельзя кстати — от Гомера до Фридмана, от зарождения понятия «Европа», до очередного кризиса этой идеи.

А в начале марта поеду в Афины, так сказать, соединю это всё с реальностью, своего рода x-phi на родине самой философии.

Получил сегодня отлично по Русской философии.
Поэтому просто не имею морального права не сказать:

Рамзан Кадыров — позор России.

https://www.facebook.com/leonid.m.volkov/posts/1018423114846988

Очень точное наблюдение в New York Times. А следующая стадия после встраивания в институты современной науки это вообще отказ от философии, как это например в Японии происходит.

И это очень печальный и опасный процесс: философ как ролевая модель умирает.


New York Times: http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2016/01/11/when-philosophy-lost-its-way/:
«The history of Western philosophy can be presented in a number of ways. It can be told in terms of periods — ancient, medieval and modern. We can divide it into rival traditions (empiricism versus rationalism, analytic versus Continental), or into various core areas (metaphysics, epistemology, ethics). It can also, of course, be viewed through the critical lens of gender or racial exclusion, as a discipline almost entirely fashioned for and by white European men.

The philosopher’s hands were never clean and were never meant to be.

Yet despite the richness and variety of these accounts, all of them pass over a momentous turning point: the locating of philosophy within a modern institution (the research university) in the late 19th century. This institutionalization of philosophy made it into a discipline that could be seriously pursued only in an academic setting. This fact represents one of the enduring failures of contemporary philosophy.

Take this simple detail: Before its migration to the university, philosophy had never had a central home. Philosophers could be found anywhere — serving as diplomats, living off pensions, grinding lenses, as well as within a university. Afterward, if they were “serious” thinkers, the expectation was that philosophers would inhabit the research university. Against the inclinations of Socrates, philosophers became experts like other disciplinary specialists. This occurred even as they taught their students the virtues of Socratic wisdom, which highlights the role of the philosopher as the non-expert, the questioner, the gadfly.

Philosophy, then, as the French thinker Bruno Latour would have it, was “purified” — separated from society in the process of modernization. This purification occurred in response to at least two events. The first was the development of the natural sciences, as a field of study clearly distinct from philosophy, circa 1870, and the appearance of the social sciences in the decade thereafter. Before then, scientists were comfortable thinking of themselves as “natural philosophers” — philosophers who studied nature; and the predecessors of social scientists had thought of themselves as “moral philosophers.”

The second event was the placing of philosophy as one more discipline alongside these sciences within the modern research university. A result was that philosophy, previously the queen of the disciplines, was displaced, as the natural and social sciences divided the world between them.

This is not to claim that philosophy had reigned unchallenged before the 19th century. The role of philosophy had shifted across the centuries and in different countries. But philosophy in the sense of a concern about who we are and how we should live had formed the core of the university since the church schools of the 11th century. Before the development of a scientific research culture, conflicts among philosophy, medicine, theology and law consisted of internecine battles rather than clashes across yawning cultural divides. Indeed, these older fields were widely believed to hang together in a grand unity of knowledge — a unity directed toward the goal of the good life. But this unity shattered under the weight of increasing specialization by the turn of the 20th century.

Early 20th-century philosophers thus faced an existential quandary: With the natural and social sciences mapping out the entirety of both theoretical as well as institutional space, what role was there for philosophy? A number of possibilities were available: Philosophers could serve as 1) synthesizers of academic knowledge production; 2) formalists who provided the logical undergirding for research across the academy; 3) translators who brought the insights of the academy to the world at large; 4) disciplinary specialists who focused on distinctively philosophical problems in ethics, epistemology, aesthetics and the like; or 5) as some combination of some or all of these.

If philosophy was going to have a secure place in the academy, it needed its own discrete domain, its own arcane language, its own standards of success and its own specialized concerns.

There might have been room for all of these roles. But in terms of institutional realities, there seems to have been no real choice. Philosophers needed to embrace the structure of the modern research university, which consists of various specialties demarcated from one another. That was the only way to secure the survival of their newly demarcated, newly purified discipline. “Real” or “serious” philosophers had to be identified, trained and credentialed. Disciplinary philosophy became the reigning standard for what would count as proper philosophy.

This was the act of purification that gave birth to the concept of philosophy most of us know today. As a result, and to a degree rarely acknowledged, the institutional imperative of the university has come to drive the theoretical agenda. If philosophy was going to have a secure place in the academy, it needed its own discrete domain, its own arcane language, its own standards of success and its own specialized concerns.

Having adopted the same structural form as the sciences, it’s no wonder philosophy fell prey to physics envy and feelings of inadequacy. Philosophy adopted the scientific modus operandi of knowledge production, but failed to match the sciences in terms of making progress in describing the world. Much has been made of this inability of philosophy to match the cognitive success of the sciences. But what has passed unnoticed is philosophy’s all-too-successful aping of the institutional form of the sciences. We, too, produce research articles. We, too, are judged by the same coin of the realm: peer-reviewed products. We, too, develop sub-specializations far from the comprehension of the person on the street. In all of these ways we are so very “scientific.”

Our claim, then, can be put simply: Philosophy should never have been purified. Rather than being seen as a problem, “dirty hands” should have been understood as the native condition of philosophic thought — present everywhere, often interstitial, essentially interdisciplinary and transdisciplinary in nature. Philosophy is a mangle. The philosopher’s hands were never clean and were never meant to be.

There is another layer to this story. The act of purification accompanying the creation of the modern research university was not just about differentiating realms of knowledge. It was also about divorcing knowledge from virtue. Though it seems foreign to us now, before purification the philosopher (and natural philosopher) was assumed to be morally superior to other sorts of people. The 18th-century thinker Joseph Priestley wrote “a Philosopher ought to be something greater and better than another man.” Philosophy, understood as the love of wisdom, was seen as a vocation, like the priesthood. It required significant moral virtues (foremost among these were integrity and selflessness), and the pursuit of wisdom in turn further inculcated those virtues. The study of philosophy elevated those who pursued it. Knowing and being good were intimately linked. It was widely understood that the point of philosophy was to become good rather than simply to collect or produce knowledge.

As the historian Steven Shapin has noted, the rise of disciplines in the 19th century changed all this. The implicit democracy of the disciplines ushered in an age of “the moral equivalence of the scientist” to everyone else. The scientist’s privileged role was to provide the morally neutral knowledge needed to achieve our goals, whether good or evil. This put an end to any notion that there was something uplifting about knowledge. The purification made it no longer sensible to speak of nature, including human nature, in terms of purposes and functions. By the late 19th century, Kierkegaard and Nietzsche had proved the failure of philosophy to establish any shared standard for choosing one way of life over another. This is how Alasdair MacIntyre explained philosophy’s contemporary position of insignificance in society and marginality in the academy. There was a brief window when philosophy could have replaced religion as the glue of society; but the moment passed. People stopped listening as philosophers focused on debates among themselves.

Once knowledge and goodness were divorced, scientists could be regarded as experts, but there are no morals or lessons to be drawn from their work. Science derives its authority from impersonal structures and methods, not the superior character of the scientist. The individual scientist is no different from the average Joe; he or she has, as Shapin has written, “no special authority to pronounce on what ought to be done.” For many, science became a paycheck, and the scientist became a “de-moralized” tool enlisted in the service of power, bureaucracy and commerce.

Here, too, philosophy has aped the sciences by fostering a culture that might be called “the genius contest.” Philosophic activity devolved into a contest to prove just how clever one can be in creating or destroying arguments. Today, a hyperactive productivist churn of scholarship keeps philosophers chained to their computers. Like the sciences, philosophy has largely become a technical enterprise, the only difference being that we manipulate words rather than genes or chemicals. Lost is the once common-sense notion that philosophers are seeking the good life — that we ought to be (in spite of our failings) model citizens and human beings. Having become specialists, we have lost sight of the whole. The point of philosophy now is to be smart, not good. It has been the heart of our undoing.»

Новый год в Кёльне. Место там около собора и вокзала и правда злачное даже днём, но чтобы так.

http://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-35231046

В Германии всё только начинается в этом плане: из почти 1 млн принятых мигрантов в 2015 больше половины это молодые мусульмане мужчины.

И если немецкие власти ничего делать не будут, то это неминуемо к эскалации насилия приведёт, включая жёсткие погромы мусульман правыми.

2015: новогоднее

С Новым годом | Happy New Year | Feliz Año Nuevo | 新年好 | Bonne année!

Книга года: Temple Grandin, Richard Panek, «The Autistic Brain: helping different kinds of minds succeed»

Впечатление года: было много новых стран и разных путешествий, больше всего запомнилось: переплытый Гибралтар по пути из Испании в Марокко, пролив Кука во время поездки по Новой Зеландии и Австралии, Соловки и метафизика русского леса на Русском Севере.

Город года: и снова было столько разных, что трудно выбрать только один, поэтому пусть будут наиболее зацепившие какие-то тайные струны моей души — Фес, Сидней, Сортавала.

Преодоление года: пробежал свой первый горный ультрамарафон — Eiger Ultra Trail E51 в Бернских Альпах.

Песня года: Дельфин — Мне нужен враг

«Вдруг вспыхнувшая фейерверком ярость
И ринутся на чёрта чёрт
В дурацких колпаках чтоб зло расхохоталось
Начнёт ржаветь в крови железо кулаков
На прочность пробуя гранитных лиц упрямство
И выйдет злоба из безумия берегов
И ненависти воцарится пьянство
И глядя на того кто падал в пустоту
Забвения больного поражения
Увижу лишь себя лежащим на полу
И умоляющим о чуде воскрешения»

В начале мая 2014-го я писал: «Настроение примерно такое же, как и погода, даже несмотря на хорошо проведённый отпуск. И я имею в виду не настроение сего дня, а глобальное настроение даже не всего 2014-го, а последних двух месяцев.
И ведь худшее для страны ещё впереди — вот что тревожит и угнетает больше всего. И совершенно непонятно как с этим всем жить.»

И ведь, к сожалению, должен вновь констатировать: худшее для страны ещё впереди — вот что тревожит и угнетает больше всего.
Но надо продолжать жить и бороться, несмотря ни на что.

Закат года: Соловки.
Всю неделю до прилёта туда там была штормовая погода, ливни, паромы на остров не ходили (про самолёты не проверял), собственно, и лета-то там не было весь год, но в день прилёта оно внезапно наступило и это был первый, самый потрясающий закат после многодневной непогоды.

20150816_212707

Wendelstein 7-X

В прошлый четверг, 10 декабря, получена первая плазма на новом стеллараторе Wendelstein 7-X – 1 мг гелия разогрели до температуры в 1 млн кельвинов. Пока время удержания плазмы короткое — всего 0.1 секунды, но в планах до 30 минут удерживать. Проектная температура плазмы при этом 60 — 130 млн кельвинов. Для сравнения: температура ядра Солнца составляет 15.7 млн кельвинов.